In the mid-1970s
American psychologist, Stanley Milgram wrote a book that attempted to explain the
findings of his infamous obedience experiments that had taken place more than a
decade earlier. In the experiments a sizeable number of quite ordinary people
had shown their willingness to inflict what they believed were excruciatingly painful,
possibly lethal, electric shocks on innocent strangers. In Obedience
to Authority, Milgram developed the concept of the “agentic state” to explain the
frighteningly powerful hold of obedience – subjects had entered a psychological
state where they became unthinking agents for people of higher status. Milgram,
and others, deployed the agentic state to explain why terrible atrocities occur
so regularly when the people that carry them out are often not monstrous,
psychopathic individuals, oblivious to the pain of others.
In actual fact the
agentic state is far better at illuminating far more mundane social relationships.
As one contemporary psychologist puts it: “Forget
Nazis; think of workers who bend to the will of employers when told to ignore
evidence that their product is unsafe.” Or, indeed, workers who bend to the
will of employers generally; all workers, in other words.
Milgram thought that
obedience was humanity’s “fatal flaw”, one implanted in people by aeons of
evolution. In The
Disobedient Society I take the opposite
tack – asking what if obedience is a product of social development, not
biology. If so, is a disobedient society possible?
The following is an
interview about the book published by New Compass
Why have you chosen to write a book about
obedience in 2019? The concept itself seems to be something of the old days. Hasn’t
the ‘obedience’ that people previously performed in schools, hospitals, the
workplace and the like, been replaced by subtle forms of oppression and
domination?
I think
obedience is subtle actually. I don’t think obedience entails knuckling under
because someone orders you to do something and threatens terrible consequences
if you don’t. It’s more complicated than that. In my opinion, obedience
involves an element of collusion on the part of the obedient person. That is to
say, they might not agree with the contents of the acts they are asked to perform,
but they feel they ought to – morally should – obey. That’s something different
to outright coercion.
According
to the neoliberal thinkers who really define our age (people like Hayek and
Milton Friedman), obedience is confined
to the past, however. It’s limited to chattel slavery, feudalism, communism, and,
in their view, 20th century ‘socialism’. But once the economy is
liberated from archaic or state-imposed forms of intervention and control,
obedience simply vanishes. Society merely becomes a reflection of our innermost
desires, represented by the innumerable contracts we agree with other free
individuals.
However,
this is a complete misnomer. I think obedience is actually stronger than ever.
It’s primarily evident in the labour contract which is, in essence, the promise
of obedience in exchange for wages, the means of life. In the book, I go back
to the 20th century psychologist Stanley Milgram (who conducted the
famous ‘electric shock’ experiments in the 1960s and later wrote a book about
why people obey). He concluded that, in order to work effectively, obedience
has to be based on “voluntary entry”. Milgram said people have to choose to
enter what he termed the “agentic state”; willingly becoming an agent for a
person of higher status. Without this aura of free will, compliance can only be
achieved by perpetual surveillance.
I think
that’s an important insight into why wage labour, which is now absolutely
ubiquitous, works so effectively. As the 19th century economist, Henry
George said, it’s slavery “under the forms of freedom”. And the ideology of
freedom that surrounds it – the feeling that we voluntarily agree to wage
labour so therefore it must be devoid of all relations of control – is integral
to its functioning.
Of course,
I don’t for a second subscribe to the notion that wage labour is, in reality, a
genuinely voluntary transaction. Most of us have no choice but to
rent ourselves to others in order procure the means to survive or care for others. But wage
labour has, very assiduously, been given the patina of a voluntary transaction
– because if it is widely perceived as voluntary then obedience should
naturally follow because the employee feels they have moral obligation to obey.
They have signed a contract after all.
I’m not
discounting the role that bare coercion plays by the way. But the fact that we
all – or the vast majority of us – go along with this process is crucial as
well. Murray Bookchin said that “epistemologies of rule” are at once subjective
and material – i.e. rule works both by creating a system of material control
that is very difficult to resist and by organizing the “psychic structures” of
individuals so that they conform.
Milgram
also noted that obedience, despite its reputation, doesn’t take the form of “a dramatic
confrontation of opposed wills or philosophies”. Rather it inhabits career
aspirations, work relationships and technical routines. Obedience has far more
of an everyday, almost unnoticed quality, than we want to admit.
Ok, let’s turn to
Milgram’s ‘electric shock’ experiments. You base a significant portion of your
argument on them. When I studied sociology at university, however, I learned
that these experiments were ethically dubious, and the results were
questionable. You don’t agree?
I agree they were ethically dubious (although not in the
same league as the Stanford Prison experiment with which Milgram is often
erroneously paired). Some of the original participants were traumatized by what
they believed at the time they had done. You can see some of the reactions in
the recent film, Experimenter. Ethical rules were
changed after Milgram to protect those taking part in psychological experiments
so that it’s not impossible to replicate the experiment in its entirety
nowadays.
(For people who at this point haven’t got a clue what we’re
talking about, I should say the Milgram experiment, which dated from the early
1960s, involved instructing people to administer possibly lethal electric
shocks on a stranger. About 2/3rds of participants obeyed the instructions. But
it was hoax; there were no shocks).
However, I’ve not seen persuasive evidence that the results
were invalid. There have been several ‘Milgram-esque’ experiments
in recent years and they’ve produced very similar outcomes. That said, I’m not much
interested in chewing the fat over whether Milgram really did ‘demonstrate’
that ordinary people are capable of doing horrendous things ‘under orders’. To
me that is missing the point.
Milgram undertook about 19 variations on the basic
experiment. This is something that – to my knowledge – subsequent Milgram-like
experiments haven’t done; they have just tried to replicate the original
experiment. Among the variations was one in which participants merely assisted
the person who actually delivered the ‘shocks’. In this case, obedience rates
went through the roof – they were something like 93%. That indicates to me that
the willingness (or not) of people to commit atrocities is not, on reflection,
what the Milgram experiments are really about. What they really show is the strength
of obedience to authority figures, or institutional situations, considered to
have legitimacy – what Milgram called the agentic state.
Milgram said that American liberal-democratic society did
not insulate its citizens from a propensity to commit brutalities at the behest
of malevolent authority. What he should have said is that liberal-democratic
society doesn’t insulate its citizens from obedience per se, malevolent or
otherwise. In fact it relies on it.
But Milgram didn’t only explore the conditions
under which people are willing to commit atrocities on behalf of authority, but
also when they choose to disobey? How does that influence your book?
Milgram compared obedience to being in a light sleep. It’s always
possible for the obedient person to wake up – or be woken
up. One of the most effective ways to encourage disobedience, Milgram concluded,
was other people being disobedient or “peer rebellion”. In one of the
experimental variations, actors refuse to go along with the experimenter’s
instructions to shock the victim. And when they disobey, invariably the genuine
subject does too. Paradoxically, conformity – doing what other people are doing
– is an important element in disobedience.
The lesson here is that disobedience or rebellion is rarely a solitary
event. It involves a moral transgression which normally successfully inhibits
disobedience but when growing numbers of people join in the rebellion, these
inhibitions are overcome. “The revolt against malevolent authority is most
effectively brought about by collective rather than individual action,” said
Milgram. “This is a lesson every revolutionary group learns.”
Your book doesn’t only revolve around Milgram’s experiments and his
takes on obedience. You also present your own views on how obedience has become
‘naturalized’ through history, and it’s evolution with capitalism. Could you
sum up your analysis of this?
There is a definite ‘so what’
quality to Milgram’s view of obedience despite the illumination his experiments
impart. If you totally buy in to his world view you could imagine conducting a
similar experiment in 2119 – or whenever – and producing virtually identical
results. That’s because Milgram believed obedience was a fatal flaw in human nature
or, to use his actual, rather cold-blooded, words, has been “bred into the
organism through the extended operation of evolutionary processes”. A capacity for obedience is in all of us and
the only defence against it, in Milgram’s eyes, is to be aware of its
existence.
This is where I part company with
Milgram – thankfully for the book which would have been rather pointless
otherwise! Obedience is definitely deeply ingrained but it’s not, in my
opinion, genetic. It’s a product of social history, not biology. In the book, I
go back to early human history – late Paleolithic times – in an attempt to
demonstrate that human society was not always hierarchical and rooted in command
and obedience.
For instance, Bookchin examined the
characteristics of what he termed “organic society” – hunter-gatherer and
scavenging bands that existed before the arrival of agriculture. He concluded
that they practiced an “ethics of complementarity”, rather than separating
people into subordinate and superordinate roles. They ensured everyone had an “inalienable
right” to food, shelter and clothing and followed usufruct – the idea that the
resources of the community belonged to the user as long as s/he needed them.
I’m well aware that Bookchin has
been criticized for painting far too rosy a picture of early humanity. In
particular for basing his conclusions on surviving tribal societies – e.g.
Australian aborigines – and assuming humans 30,000 years ago were just like
them. However, serious investigations of the nature of upper Paleolithic
society (which is not a simple matter) have – while not totally validating
Bookchin – discounted the idea that obedience has always been part of us, that
it’s an evolutionary adaptation. For instance, David Wengrow and David Graeber, who have attempted to fuse the
insights of archaeology and anthropology, assert that hunter-gatherers
consciously alternated between political forms according to the seasons – for
instance submitting to coercive authority in winter but dispersing into smaller,
egalitarian groups in summer. Hence an awareness was implanted that “no social order was immutable: that
everything was at least potentially open to negotiation, subversion and change”.
I think we need to have a better
understanding of where biology ends and social history begins – at the moment
the slide rule, following Milgram and many others subsequently, is far too far
towards the biology end.
I believe Bookchin’s concept of
first and second nature – which I elaborate in the book – is much more
credible. I’m amazed actually it hasn’t been accorded greater attention. First
nature is a strictly biological realm – humans are part of first nature, we are
mammals and primates and are moulded by evolution to intervene collectively and
intentionally in the natural world. This is not a ‘blank slate’ argument. But
we also have a second nature which is creative and open-ended. Hence the
character of our “collective organization” is not preordained by nature.
Societies – as history shows – can take many different forms and will in the
future. Obedience is not written in our genes.
Milgram would counter that though
societies change and mutate, obedience is a constant. We learn obedience in
early life and then, as adults, function within hierarchical organizations. And
if malevolent forces capture the commanding heights of these hierarchies, then
this ‘natural’ obedience can engender nightmares.
However, an opposing view, as I’ve
outlined, is actually more plausible. Early humanity didn’t inhabit fixed,
hierarchical structures and hierarchy, once it developed as civilization spread,
was always accompanied by its subterranean nemesis. Unquestionably obedience
and hierarchy have been the dominant characteristics of society for thousands
of years. They are extremely durable. But an opposite way of being was never
entirely eradicated. And sporadically, it could break out into the open, as
evidenced by the direct democracy of ancient Athens or the council systems of
the famous revolutions – the French, Russian and German etc. These democratic
councils were not created by political parties and, though wiped out, aspired
to permanence. Thus, another world – a disobedient society – is possible.
Where capitalism fits in to this
picture is, as I’ve said earlier, in the realm of ideology. The ‘free’ labourer
who sells their services on the market was seen as the antithesis of obedience
because once we enter the realm of contracting with others, everything is seen
to flow from our own desires. But this is a fiction – obedience has merely been
camouflaged. Not to mention that ‘unfree’ labour – e.g. prison or migrant
labour – is more important to capitalism than is often given credit for. But
that’s another story.
In the book, it seems like you argue that obedience isn’t just a matter
of ideology, but also of material conditions – and that today’s technological
development may make wage labour obsolete. Is that a correct interpretation?
Obedience, I argue, is in part a
collateral effect of economic organization. So the corporation, our signature
economic entity, embodies obedience – it is organized as a pyramid with senior
managers reporting to a board of directors and below them workers obeying
precise orders from above. It is held together by a career structure in which
promotion is conditional on appraisal by superiors. Promotion was regarded by
Milgram as an “ingenious” way of preserving hierarchical structures because it
has such a motivational effect on the individual. A “profound emotional
gratification”, he observed, is inculcated in those who successfully climb the
ladder.
But any system of material control
and oppression isn’t really seen in its true light until it is also regarded as
economically superfluous. So in the 19th century temporary wage labour gradually replaced
chattel slavery as the economically rational social arrangement, embodied in
the joint stock company, later called the corporation. Wage labour brought in
its train terrible suffering – disease, overcrowding, malnutrition – but, apart
from the socialist movement, few people wanted to dispense with it (some wanted
to ameliorate it) because it was seen as crucial for wealth creation and
productivity.
Now, however, you can observe that
technological advancements – for example, 3D printing – are theoretically
making human input into the production process much less important. So wage
labour, which is all about the necessity of human involvement in the production
process, should decline as well. American social theorist, Jeremy Rifkin – who
is no leftist – predicts that in a few decades’ time people will look upon wage
labour with the same sense of utter disbelief that we now reserve for slavery
and serfdom – as something “primitive, even barbaric” and a “terrible loss of
human value”. But this enlightenment will only occur once wage labour is seen
as unnecessary.
You can in theory predict that as
economic organization changes, obedience will fade away. As robots become
capable of cognitive, as well as physical tasks, and miniaturization and
nanotechnology develop, centralized, large-scale production will be superseded
and the kind of human being needed to make that sort of production function
will die out.
However, before we get too excited
about what awaits us, it’s worth considering things which militate against that
happening. Firstly, the economic system that surrounds us – capitalism – is no
longer capable, in my opinion, of delivering epoch shattering technological
change. Productivity and business investment are at historical lows and the
gale of creative destruction has given way to an oppressive stillness. So, to happen, radical
technological change needs a different economic system.
Secondly, material change doesn’t automatically rule out the continuation of obedience. Economic entities could still function without much human input, leaving the vast majority of the population to scrap over the remaining jobs (although that scenario has obvious problems with effective demand). Or obedience could continue in a non-material way, going back, in a way, to how it first started.
All you can say is that
technological change – or the possibility of it occurring – does represent an
opportunity for those of us who believe in an egalitarian, non-obedient future.
For some, one opportunity that arises from our present day technological
advancement is universal basic income (UBI). You are also a proponent of UBI,
but so are also several people on the liberal right. Thus, this proposal
remains controversial on the Left. How does UBI fit into your indisputably
Leftist vision of a disobedient society?
I support unconditional basic income
almost by default. One of the book’s basic arguments is that wage labour –
though it is presented as a voluntary transaction – is really a continuation of
the obedience of the past. It involves obeying the instructions of someone of
higher status in return for the gift of life – money to live on. I align with
one of the notions of classical republicanism that a person is not free if
subject to another’s will, regardless of how that subjection came about and
whether the person somehow voluntarily chose it.
So if the problem is this
fundamental unfreedom you can’t solve it by making everyone an employee of a
socialist state or even by transforming the economy into a collection of
worker-controlled enterprises. A free society has to involve independence for
everyone, which implies untrammelled access to the means of life, which implies
an unconditional basic income – what
Erich Fromm called “the right to live, regardless”.
I’m from the UK and I’m painfully
aware that the removal of a person’s income is now a major plank of government
policy, in that it is seen as an essential threat to motivate people to accept
any kind of paid employment. Sanctions (the taking away of all benefits for a set
period) are widespread and a ‘Work Capability Assessment’ ensures that disabled
and ill people are often denied any kind of financial assistance at all. The UK
welfare state, now more accurately classed as a punishment state, has been
described as “an insult to human freedom” and I agree. In such circumstances,
the priority
must be giving people security of income, which is another way of
saying a basic income.
Yes, elements of the liberal Right –
Silicon Valley billionaires and corporate ‘thought leaders’ like Richard
Branson – are in favour of a basic income. The thinking here is that in future
the main source of work will be serving the billionaire class in some way and
that, with the disappearance of traditional permanent employment and
employments rights, people will need a minimum of income to survive. Hence
calls for a basic income at a rudimentary level; “continuous income for
discontinuous work”. But there is another kind of larger basic income which is
intended to be sufficient for people to engage in “multi-activity” – political,
participatory, sporting, artistic etc. If a genuinely participatory society
ever comes about, it would have to be buttressed, in my opinion, by a large
basic income simply to give people the time to participate.
To be honest, as society is
presently structured, the only kind of basic income I can see on the horizon is
the first kind. But given the problem of complete destitution in putatively rich countries, maybe
even that will be a form of progress.
So, universal basic income is one element of what you call a
‘disobedient society’. What other elements does this vision consist of? And why
do you use the phrase ‘disobedient society’ in the first place?
The most important element is
participation in political and economic affairs. At present we live under – if
we are lucky – a very limited version of democracy. We usually spend the
majority of our lives within hierarchical, dictatorially-organized institutions
and give our consent every few years to a suite of policies – austerity,
liberalized financial markets, low corporate taxes, for example – that actually
we may violently disagree with. In fact, this bestowing of consent seems
absolutely crucial to the rulers of society, much like forced labour or ‘modern
slavery’ is seen as totally beyond the pale. There has to be an element of
voluntarism – however empty – about the whole process.
However there is another form of
democracy. In contrast to periodically electing a representative – who may well
simply conform to the dictates of seemingly immovable national and global
elites – the idea is to seek the wishes and desires of people at the base of
society and then transmit them upwards through a series of levels or councils.
Officials (chair-person, secretary) are frequently rotated and delegates can be
recalled if they don’t faithfully amplify the views of people they are intended
to give voice to. It’s a living system, as opposed to the ossified institutions
of liberal-democracy, in which the practice
of democracy is as important as any outcome. It can be observed in operation in
Rojava in North-East Syria, despite the fact that the revolution there is under
concerted physical attack.
This council system of democracy
also has also unfailingly cropped up in every major revolution in modern history
– the French, Russian and German for example. It has been termed the “lost
treasure” of the revolutionary tradition by philosopher Hannah Arendt. Unquestionably
these councils were set upon by conservative forces and the authoritarian Left,
and this is a major reason why their existence was so ephemeral. But they were
also swimming against the tide of inescapably economically scarce conditions.
“There was”, as I say in the book, “a palpable discrepancy between their
ambition – that everyone who wishes to should be able to participate in the
forming of public policy and the future course of society – and the economic
realities that surrounded them.” They were, in a way, before their time.
A
genuinely participatory system requires time, or leisure as the ancient
Athenians put it. If universal free time does not exist, and the vast majority
of people are engulfed in working to make a living, participatory structures,
should they exist, will always struggle and succumb to, at best, more consensual
forms of democracy. But if technological change enables work-time to be
radically reduced, then the council democracy of past revolutions might not be
seen as fleeting utopian outbursts, but as harbingers of the future.
The
phrase “a disobedient society” might appear to be an oxymoron – in fact that’s
why I employ it. To Stanley Milgram and many other others, society had to
involve obedience. If obedience was absent, society couldn’t function. But that
is precisely what I dispute. Obedience is unthinkingly following the
instructions of people of higher status. It’s unknowing and irrational and
involves deliberately closing your mind – an “alteration of attitude” as
Milgram phrased it. But disobedience does not imply the end of discipline,
coordination or episodic sovereignty. It does not mean anarchy in a pejorative
sense. It merely involves the rational acceptance of temporary authority for
agreed purposes.
A disobedient society can still be conformist
by the way. Conformity – mirroring the thought or behaviour of peers – is not
the same as obedience which involves carrying out instructions of
‘superiors’ regardless of whether you
agree with them or not. Conformity is the hidden danger of a disobedient
society and is why I’m a strong believer in Bookchin’s concept of dissensus. But a
disobedient society is not a contradiction in terms.
I’m
not overly optimistic. Some very powerful people and forces will devote all
their energy to snuffing out any moves in this direction. They are doing now. But the reason I wrote
the book was to point out that ‘human nature’ itself is not a fatal obstacle to
a disobedient society coming about. As the slogan goes, ‘Another World is Possible’.
Not probable and certainly not inevitable. But it is possible.
No comments:
Post a Comment